公 法 评 论   http://www.gongfa.com/

        The F.A. Hayek Memorial Lecture

Austrian Scholars Conference

Auburn, Alabama

2001

 

 

Two Constructions of Libertarianism

Chandran Kukathas

 

kukathas@one.net.au

 

I

Libertarians believe that all individuals are entitled to live as they choose, free from

interference by other persons or by the state. They also believe that in the absence of such

interference, whether by government or other agents of the state intent on designing or

planning for society as a whole, order will nonetheless prevail. Given the freedom to

contract and exchange, markets will coordinate the production and distribution of goods

— and indeed do so better than any other institution can. But it is the first belief that is

theoretically distinctive, and distinguishes libertarians from others, such as free-market

utilitarians like Jeremy Bentham. For libertarians think that what is most important is to

2

defend the freedom of individuals to live without being victims of aggression by others

— against their persons, or against the property they have rightly acquired.

Two early statements by thinkers held in high esteeem in the libertarian tradition put

the point very plainly. The Leveller, Richard Overton, in ‘An Arrow Against All

Tyrants’, wrote:

To every individual in nature is given an individual property by nature, not to be

invaded or usurped by any: for everyone as he is himself, so he hath a selfpropriety,

else could he not be himself, and on this no second may presume to

deprive any of, without manifest violation and affront to the very principles of

nature…

In other words, all individuals are self owners. And self-ownership carries with it the

freedom to own property. The most famous statement of this view is Locke’s:

Though the earth, and all inferior creatures be common to all men, yet every man

has a property in his own person. This nobody has any right to but himself. The

labour of his body, and the work of his hands, we may say, are properly his.

Whatsoever then he removes out of the state that nature hath provided, and left it

in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and

thereby makes it his property.’

In short, all individuals must have liberty; but only that liberty that is consistent with a

respect for the liberty and property of others. And this is the basis of the libertarian

account of the justification for, and role of, the state. If individuals own themselves, and

have a right not be aggressed against by others, no government is legitimate unless it has

3

the consent of the people. (For some libertarians, it is then simply a matter of logic to

show by inference that no government is legitimate.) For those libertarians who think

there is a role for government, its purpose cannot be to improve people, or attend to their

welfare, or satisfy their needs, or give them what they deserve. At most, its purpose is to

protect individual liberty against invasion by others, whether at home or from abroad.

Otherwise, it should leave people alone. What could be simpler?

Yet matters may not be quite so straightforward. For there is more than one kind of

society that could issue from such simple beginnings. Indeed, there are at least two very

different societies which might be constructed out of such libertarian first principles. And

it must be asked, first, which of these is the one that libertarians ought to prefer; and,

second, whether either of them is wholly acceptable from a libertarian point of view. To

be a libertarian is to attach especial importance — if not overriding value — to liberty.

Which, if either, of the societies produced by libertarian principles is acceptable from the

standpoint of liberty? That is the question to be explored here.

II

Let us begin by imagining the first society, called the Federation of Liberty. In this

society it is recognized that aggression is fundamentally wrong, for ‘no man or group of

men have the right to aggress against the person or property of anyone else.’ Aggression

is recognized to mean ‘the initiation of the use or threat of physical violence against the

person or property of someone else.’ This society recognizes ‘the absolute right to private

property of every man; first, in his own body, and second, in the previously unused

4

natural resources which he first transforms by his labour.’ In other words, it recognizes

two central axioms: the right to self-ownership and the right to ‘homestead’.

Now the world is a diverse place, and people have different ideas about what is good

and about what is right. The intuition libertarianism as a moral doctrine seeks to capture

is the thought that when people differ in their ideas about what is good or right it is wrong

to try to force people to accept one version or another, particularly if they are prepared

simply to go their separate ways. Aggression — the initiation of the use or threat of

physical violence — is never defensible. The use of force is permissible only in defence

of one’s person or property.

But the world being a diverse place, it will include not only people who accept the

principles of libertarianism but also those who don’t. What should be libertarianism’s

attitude to those who disagree with libertarian principles? In the Federation of Liberty the

answer is that the principle of libertarianism should be extended to cover not simply the

treatment of those who believe in it but the treatment of all persons. That is to say, it

would tolerate in its midst even those who do not accept the principles of libertarianism.

Such persons are free to go about their business unimpeded, provided that they do not

aggress against others. If they are numerous enough, they might form their own

communities or groups, and live by their own lights. If they will not aggress against

libertarians, then libertarians will not aggress against them.

The consequence of this attitude in the Federation of Liberty might well be that there

are quite a few groups or communities which not only disregard but directly repudiate

libertarian principles. These may be communities in which the right to hold private

property is not recognized, or in which the freedom of the individual to dissent from the

5

community’s powerful authorities is not respected — or even conceded. Indeed, the

freedom of the individual to leave the community or group may not be accepted, so that

many people are effectively held within the community against their will. And this is not

to mention those who are kept within these communities in ignorance of any possibility

of leaving for a society in which they might make use freedoms they do not enjoy here.

But in the Federation of Liberty, those libertarians who do hold to libertarian

principles will do nothing, for they cannot aggress against others except in self-defence.

Or at least, that is how the principles of libertarianism are understood here. It simply is

not permissible to initiate the use of force against others who are not threatening to use

force against you or your property. Here libertarians really can do very little about those

who repudiate libertarianism and work to perpetuate ways of living that do not respect or

value liberty. They may, for example, attempt to inform or educate those who are

ignorant of their libertarian rights that they do not have to remain among people who

have no regard for them. But if those who control the communities in which libertarian

rights are dishonoured do not permit this, libertarians are not at liberty to march in and

force them to allow everyone to listen to the outsiders. Libertarians might be free to

broadcast messages — on Radio Liberty or on the Libertarian News Network — but

cannot demand that their signals not be blocked or, for that matter, that the targets of their

transmissions be allowed to watch and listen.

If the account so far is right, there could be a great deal of unfreedom in the Federation

of Liberty. The principle of non-aggression in this society produces a society which is

characterised by a non-aggression pact among people, some of whom do, and others of

whom do not, accept the principles of libertarianism. But in fact such a society might

6

exhibit even less liberty still. For under this understanding of libertarianism it is quite

possible, in principle, for the Federation of Liberty to be made up of only a minority of

persons who accept the principle of non-aggression, if a majority of persons live in

groups where aggression within the group is condoned or unchecked. Indeed it is

possible, in principle, that no one accepts the principles of libertarianism. The principle of

non-aggression operates only between groups or communities, since no one will use force

to intervene in the activities of those whose actions do not aggress against them or their

property.

But can this really be a libertarian society? One reason it might be alleged that it is not

is that this is a society which does not so much respect individual rights as uphold group

rights. And there is nothing in the libertarian canon that requires the recognition of the

rights of groups. Yet in the Federation of Liberty there are no group rights. None of the

communities which comprise it may claim anything from others on the basis of any group

status or collective identity. Groups have no right even to keep their members within their

borders; and if those who escape from groups they find oppressive find sanctuary among

others outside, no one is under any obligation to force them to return and no one has any

right that they be returned. No one may use force against these individuals to make them

live among those with whom they have no wish to associate. Though, equally, no one

may use force to extricate them from communities which deprive those persons of liberty

or of the knowledge that they have rights. Only individuals have rights; groups do not.

Though evidently this does not stop groups from having power; or prevent individuals

from becoming powerless.

7

In such a society individuals not enjoy liberty for either of two reasons. In the first

instance, they might not enjoy freedom because they have no longing for it, having been

raised in their associations or communities with no knowledge that this is something

desirable. Some forms of religious education do this quite well. And we know that in

many societies particular classes of people are raised to understand that social roles are

given by nature. Women, for example, have in many places been raised to accept that

they were not free to choose the path their lives must take. In such circumstances, people

do not enjoy freedom because neither circumstances nor their fellows have revealed to

them that freedom is desirable. (Of course, many may naturally seek liberty. I do not wish

to deny this. But for the purposes of my argument it is sufficient to point out that some

will not be possessed of a natural longing for freedom powerful to overcome the effects

of socialisation to the contrary.)

The second reason individuals might not enjoy freedom in a society like the

Federation of Liberty is that they are prevented from doing so. In such cases, individuals

might long for freedom but not be able to attain it because they are forcibly prevented

from doing so. Some might be indentured labourers working to pay off a debt of which

they will never be rid because they have accepted punitive terms when borrowing. (In a

sense they might have been forced to do so, since the monopoly powers granted to

lenders in the community leaves borrowers no option of choosing among competitive

interest rates.) In other cases, people might have inherited debts because custom requires

that debts be passed on to children. At the extreme case, people might be unfree because

they are literally enslaved and slavery is acceptable in the community — which is a

8

community that does not believe in libertarian principles. Such people might want to

leave — it is almost certain that they would — but they are prevented from doing so.

Such unfreedom is possible in the Federation of Liberty because the practice of nonaggression

is understood to require that people not intervene in the activities of others

except in defence of their own rights and property. Thus while those whose liberty has

been infringed may be entitled to resist those who are trying to impede them, no one else

may aggress against those who are violating the rights of others. In any case, most people

are reluctant to get involved with those parts of the society where liberty is less than

completely enjoyed: free trade with all, but entanglements with none is the catch-cry that

would be heard — except that people minding their own business usually have no catchcries.

Though people crying out for help find this less than comforting.

Now, one way around this problem for the defenders of the Federation of Liberty as a

genuinely libertarian society would be to point out that it is always open to an individual

to appoint an agent — or indeed many agents — to act on his behalf. Anyone deprived of

his liberty or aggressed against can appoint agents to act on his behalf to protect his

rights. These agents would not be aggressing against a third party without cause, for they

are agents of the principal acting in self-defence. If this were the case, it would be

justified in the Federation of Liberty for many of those whose rights have been violated

to be rescued from communities or persons guilty of aggression against others. But this

does not resolve the problem of what happens to those who are unable to appoint agents

to act for them. Even in a world of entrepreneurial would-be agents looking for principals

needing to be freed, such potential agents have no right to demand that those they suspect

of violating rights allow them to inspect their premises or their records. Such would-be

9

agents may not use force to gain access to knowledge of rights violations, or to gain

knowledge of the wishes of people who might want to employ their services. Or at least,

not in a society like the Federation of Liberty. For it does not condone the initiation of the

use or threat of physical force against the person or property of anyone. Yet, perversely,

this turns out to be a society in which many people end up being free to use force.

The Federation of Liberty might in fact turn out to be a federation of not much liberty

at all. And from a libertarian point of view this might be a good reason to reject its

understanding of the principle of non-aggression. Perhaps the principle of non-aggression

properly understood will give us a society libertarians can commend; but that may require

a very different understanding or construction of that principle.

III

So let us imagine a second society, this one going by the name the Union of Liberty. In

this society it is recognized that aggression is fundamentally wrong, for ‘no man or group

of men have the right to aggress against the person or property of anyone else.’

Aggression is recognized to mean ‘the initiation of the use or threat of physical violence

against the person or property of someone else.’ This society recognizes ‘the absolute

right to private property of every man; first, in his own body, and second, in the

previously unused natural resources which he first transforms by his labour.’ In other

words, it recognizes two central axioms: the right to self-ownership and the right to

‘homestead’.

10

Now the world is a diverse place, and people have different ideas about what is good

and about what is right. The intuition libertarianism as a moral doctrine seeks to capture

is the thought that when people differ in their ideas about what is good or right it is wrong

to try to force people to accept one version or another, particularly if they are prepared

simply to go their separate ways. Aggression — the initiation of the use or threat of

physical violence — is never defensible. The use of force is permissible only in defence

of one’s person or property.

But the world being a diverse place, it will include not only people who accept the

principles of libertarianism but also those who don’t. What should be libertarianism’s

attitude to those who disagree with libertarian principles? In the Union of Liberty the

answer is that the principle of libertarianism is not one that people may choose not to

adopt. The principle holds for all persons, in their dealings with all persons. What is the

point, after all, of a moral principle that does not apply to all?

But what is the implication of this for the kind of society that will emerge out of such

a construction of libertarianism? It ought to be noted at the outset that it may not mean

that no non-libertarian communities or associations will exist in such a society. A crucial

dimension to the rights libertarianism prescribes is the freedom of persons to waive their

rights — or at least, some of their rights.1 Some persons might therefore agree with one

1 As an aside, let me note that some rights may not be waivable. One may not be entitled to alienate one’s

right to liberty such that one can sell oneself into slavery. The principle of non-aggression means that no

performance of an action can be compelled, even if performance has been contracted. Though, of

course, the party injured by non-performance may have a just claim to compensation. This means that

anyone selling himself into slavery cannot alienate his right to break the contract by refusing to perform

11

another to form associations in which they live, voluntarily, by non-libertarian principles.

They might agree to hold their property in common and limit private ownership; and they

might place restrictions on speech, or require all to abide by strict rules limiting what

each may do and authorising some to hold considerable power the others. What is

different about the Union of Liberty, however, is that, unlike the Federation of Liberty,

no one is permitted to live without liberty unless he has explicitly relinquished those

particular liberties he lacks.

The difference this makes is a substantial one — more so than it might at first appear.

For in the Union of Liberty, associations not founded on the consent of the governed may

not operate. This means that certain kinds of associations or communities cannot exist,

for the only legitimate associations are voluntary associations. Associations or

communities not founded on the principle of voluntary association cannot have a place in

the Union of Liberty. In the Federation of Liberty such communities or associations had a

place insofar as the principle of liberty meant a prohibition on intervention which allowed

such communities to operate. But in the Union of Liberty the principle of liberty prohibits

the operation of communities which do not respect the principle of liberty.

In this society, then, it would not be possible, say, for certain religious groups to

operate, since they effectively repudiate the principle of liberty by denying their members

any right to acquire or hold property, restricting their freedom to worship, denying them

freedom to move about, and failing to make these members aware that they have rights to

as directed, even though he would have then to compensate the person with whom he made the contract

of ‘slavery’. In effect, this means that slavery contracts cannot have any force.

12

reject their membership of such a society. The Hutterites might be an example of such a

group. Similarly, communities of aboriginal peoples who do not recognize the principle

of liberty could not be allowed to operate unless all their members willingly agreed with

the terms of the association.

In fact, in the Union of Liberty there could not be any states or provinces that

restricted liberty, say by imposing tariffs, or prohibiting the use of certain drugs, or

mandating particular educational requirements. The standard of liberty is a standard

which has to hold not only for society as a whole, but for all the societies within that

society. People may not be deprived of their liberty without their consent. No authority

can take it upon itself to deny people their freedom; and any authority which tried to do

so has to be subject to censure.

The problem is that there are a great many communities and associations which

operate without respecting the principle of liberty, or which violate the requirement of

consent. Most obviously, most dealings with children invariably involve some restriction

of their liberty, and usually without children’s consent. Parents routinely deprive their

children of liberty, either by requiring some actions or proscribing others. Parents, in

conjunction with their communities, generally work assiduously to educate their children,

not only so that they might accumulate a stock of knowledge but also to try to ensure that

they will come to hold particular values as adults. Educators try not only to develop in

children the skills they will need to be able to earn a living and to fulfil their desires, but

also to inculcate in them particular desires — and, of course, to teach them that some

desires are unworthy or immoral. The younger the children, the greater the interference

with their liberty, and less often their consent is sought.

13

Often parents and communities go further in their efforts to shape and prepare children

for later life. Some religious or cultural traditions require that children be physically

transformed, whether through forms of genital mutilation or in ritual scarring. Children

are thus subject to a variety of physical treatments, from footbinding to circumcision, in

the interests of their future welfare. All without their consent. Equally, in some traditions

children do not enjoy liberty not because they are forced to undergo particular rituals but

because certain treatments are withheld from them. Parents may believe, for example,

that blood transfusions are morally repugnant or that vaccinations are a violation of

bodily integrity, and that their children should therefore be spared such interventions.

Their children would thus grow up not only without undergoing these medical treatments

but also with no knowledge of them. Again, consent is not sought.

It is worth bearing in mind here that not only can the treatment of children vary from

community to community, or tradition to tradition, but the understanding or definition of

childhood can differ substantially from place to place. Children are routinely deprived of

liberty without their consent; but the ‘age of consent’ varies considerably as well.

Children do not fall into a ‘natural’ category, whose membership is obvious or

uncontentious.

But age is not the only basis upon which communities might restrict the application of

the principle of liberty. Some communities might do so on the basis of gender or ethnicity

or religion or sexuality. Thus women might be denied the freedom to seek an education,

or non-natives might be forbidden to own land, or those with particular sexual

orientations might be prohibited from some forms of employment or from entering into

14

certain contracts. Liberty may be restricted in many ways and for a great variety of

reasons.

In the Union of Liberty, however, such restrictions cannot be tolerated, for they run

counter to the spirit of liberty which must govern the society as a whole. Liberty can be

given up by those consenting to the actions of those who choose to deprive them of it.

But it cannot be taken away. And if a free society is to be preserved, those who would

deprive others of liberty must not be permitted to do so. Liberty must be enforced if a

libertarian society is to prevail.

The implications of this outlook, however, need to be recognized. The first, and

fundamental, implication is that there can be only one authoritative understanding of

liberty. While people may in fact have different views about liberty, only one view of

what liberty means and what liberty demands can provide the standard by which conduct

is judged. Second, and following from this, there cannot be a multiplicity of authorities

with the right to set standards of conduct. If there were more than one authority, there

could in principle be more than one understanding of liberty. Indeed, there could be

authorities which would compromise liberty in favour of other values. In a libertarian

society, however, liberty must be pre-eminent. And in the Union of Liberty, since all

societies within that society must uphold liberty, there must be a single, authoritative,

understanding of liberty or else the variation in interpretation of freedom’s meaning could

leave liberty in many places honoured only in name.

A further implication follows from this. The Union of Liberty is a society in which the

principle of non-aggression — prohibiting the initiation of the use of physical violence —

does not rule out but endorses intervention by third parties to end, or avert, aggression by

15

others. This means it is permissible to intervene in the workings of communities or

associations which do not respect libertarian principles, and whose members have not

waived their libertarian rights. It will not matter if the community in question asserts,

through its authorities, that outsiders have no jurisdiction within its borders or over its

members, or that it is improper for outsiders to aggress against them when they have not

themselves been aggressed against. For it is enough that the community is held, by the

outsiders, to be not a voluntary association but rather one in which some members are

deprived of their libertarian rights without their consent.

The implication of this, however, is quite serious. Though it will be necessary to look

more closely into the matter to see why. If intervention in the affairs of people who have

not aggressed against us is permissible — to stop aggression within their own community

— this must be either because anyone may determine whether or not intervention is

justifiable, or only when it is authorised as lawful to intervene. In the Union of Liberty, it

must be the case that intervention is permissible only when it is lawful — and authorised

as such. I say this because I am assuming that a libertarian society is a society under law.

In the Federation of Liberty, there are many communities and, so, many systems of law;

and the prohibition against intervention means that some of the systems of law will not be

libertarian in character, since they condone aggression against persons and their property.

In the Union of Liberty, if intervention is permissible to stop or avert aggression by some

against others, it must be permissible only according to law (or else the Union of Liberty

would not be a society that operates under law). But what law is this?

The law in question here cannot be the minimal rules of confederation that describes

the Federation of Liberty, which permit each community to run its own affairs — even if

16

in violation of the principles of libertarianism. For these minimal rules do not permit

intervention — aggression, or the initiation of force — except in cases of self-defence.

But the Union of Liberty condones, or even mandates, intervention — precisely to stop

aggression, or the initiation of force. Its laws must therefore reach further, specifying not

simply how communities with different laws must relate to one another, but what laws

every community must have. It must prescribe, in other words, what standards every

community must meet if it is to pass the libertarian test, for no non-libertarian community

may operate.

Now the implication of this is that there will be a central judicial body with final

authority. For it cannot be left up to each community to determine whether it meets the

libertarian test – or we would be back to the situation in which some communities fail to

meet the standards of libertarianism (but simply claim to have done so). This judicial

body will have the authority to determine when intervention is permitted to stop or avert

aggression. It will also have the authority, since there is no other superior judicial power,

to determine who may rightly intervene — to stop or avert aggression.

The problem we face now, however, is that there is in existence in the Union of

Liberty a strong central authority. This judicial power will quite possibly — indeed, is

more than likely to — be captured by the most powerful groups or communities, who will

try to influence its understanding of what libertarian law prescribes, and its determination

of where or with whom the power to intervene should lie.

The Union of Liberty might in fact turn out, then, to be a union of not much liberty at

all. For it could end up a union in which a great power ends up being established — one

capable of depriving people of their wish to live by dissenting moral standards, even if

17

they are dissenting libertarian moral standards. A libertarian orthodoxy is still an

orthodoxy. And it must be asked whether any orthodoxy in power is really an ideal of

libertarian construction.

IV

If the reasoning behind these two constructions of libertarianism is sound, the choice

confronting libertarians is an invidious one. For neither interpretation of the libertarian

first principle produces an outcome which seems particularly hospitable to liberty. The

Federation of Liberty can, in principle, turn out to contain no communities of that

federation which actually value or respect liberty; and even slavery might have a lawful

place within it. The Union of Liberty, on the other hand, can, in principle turn out to be

society ruled by a strong authority with little respect for dissenting moral traditions,

including some self-styled libertarian moral traditions. Unless some more promising

construction of libertarianism can be found to come out of its first principles, it looks as if

a choice is going to have to be made.

Alas, as I see it, no other construction of libertarianism is possible. The two

alternatives described here occupy all the available conceptual space; and there is no third

way, theoretically speaking. Libertarians must bit one bullet or another.

Given this necessity, I would argue that we should opt for the Federation of Liberty

rather than for the Union. In the time that remains I will offer a defence of this choice.

Though this defence will be incomplete, since there is surely more to be said on both

18

sides. Let me begin, however, by considering what reasons might be advanced in defence

of the Union.

The strongest argument available to the Unionist is that the Federation of Liberty fails

to respect liberty because it will tolerate unfreedom, or even slavery, in its midst. Such a

society can, in principle, be a society of communities none of which endorses or honours

libertarian principles. For this reason a libertarian Unionist would argue that a genuinely

libertarian society is one in which libertarian principles are upheld — or enforced —

everywhere. This at least will ensure that liberty is not extinguished, for aggression will

always be capable of being met by a superior power with the capacity to protect freedom.

Slavery, or other institutions limiting or dishonouring freedom, would be prohibited

without equivocation.

As a Federalist, however, I cannot help but look upon the Unionist’s claims with a

measure of scepticism. The case for the Federalist position is grounded in a conviction

that power ought not to be entrenched. While authority may be necessary in human

arrangements since disagreements have to be settled, no power should be established as

the final court of appeal from which no dissent is possible. Indeed, if anything is

fundamental to libertarianism it is the conviction that dissenters are tolerated or allowed

to go their own way — free to exit from arrangements they find intolerable themselves.

Disagreements should be addressed through efforts at persuasion rather than joined with

force. A federation of societies is a society which respects this outlook, for while it may

contain within it many authorities, none is pre-eminent, and none may subordinate the

others, or claim a right to control its members — even if some may exercise enormous

power in fact. What such a society refuses to do is bow to the temptation to control the

19

abuse of power by creating — or condoning the creation of — a greater power to enforce

right.

In the end, the establishment of power, even the power to do good, does not guarantee

that good will be done. For that matter, there is no guarantee that the Union of Liberty

will protect liberty, or even prohibit slavery. It is worth remarking that the most

libertarian constitution the world has known tried to pretend that slavery for some was

not inconsistent with the ideal of freedom for all. And the most notable defender of the

idea of a Union of Liberty was prepared to place the principle of Union above the

principle of liberty, since he would rather preserve slavery than see the Union fall.

So I defend the Federation against the Union. The choice is not, in the end, a happy

one. But philosophical choices often are of this nature, since theory frequently leads us to

reductios which are, if not absurd, unhappy or repugnant. One can only hope that in the

real world such dilemmas will be dissolved in good measure by civility and good will,

even if they cannot be resolved purely by the power of reason.